Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Mostrar: 20 | 50 | 100
Resultados 1 - 20 de 34
Filtrar
Más filtros











Base de datos
Intervalo de año de publicación
1.
Front Public Health ; 12: 1410511, 2024.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-39175899

RESUMEN

Background: The case of "a multimillionaire who was sent to a psychiatric hospital after an argument with his son" has sparked heated debate in the Chinese mainland. This incident is particularly significant as 2023 marks the 10th anniversary of the implementation of the Mental Health Law of the People's Republic of China. The focus of the ongoing debate, as brought to light by the aforementioned case, is centered on the right to refuse treatment for patients with mental disorders. Methods: This paper is a post-hoc study with a systematic analysis of literature and cases. To ascertain the relationship between the right to refuse treatment for patients with mental disorders and the Mental Health Law, the authors identified key information and data from both official government websites and reliable non-governmental information. Result: Both literature and practice have proven that the compulsory hospitalization rule under the Mental Health Law is a denial of the right to refuse treatment for patients who are compulsorily hospitalized. In the absence of changes to the law, compulsory hospitalization will inevitably lead to compulsory treatment in the Chinese mainland. Conclusion: According to the human dignity and self-determination right established in the Constitution of the People's Republic of China, patients who are compulsorily hospitalized have the right to refuse treatment. In the absence of a change in the law, given that no neutral review mechanism has been established for such patients and their treatment in the mainland, setting up an internal review mechanism is a more feasible way of protecting the right to refuse treatment for patients with mental disorders.


Asunto(s)
Trastornos Mentales , Negativa del Paciente al Tratamiento , Humanos , China , Trastornos Mentales/terapia , Negativa del Paciente al Tratamiento/legislación & jurisprudencia , Internamiento Obligatorio del Enfermo Mental/legislación & jurisprudencia , Pueblos del Este de Asia
2.
J Bioeth Inq ; 2024 Aug 14.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-39141210

RESUMEN

There is wide consensus among bioethicists about the importance of autonomy when determining whether or not a patient has the right to refuse life-saving treatment (LST). In this context, autonomy has typically been understood in terms of the patient's ability to make an informed decision. According to the traditional view, decision-making capacity (DMC) is seen as both necessary and sufficient for the right to refuse LST. Recently, this view has been challenged by those who think that considerations of authenticity and putative counterexamples should lead us to revise the traditional account. In this paper, we respond to these revisionist arguments, and we defend the traditional view according to which we have autonomy-based reasons to respect a patient's decision to refuse LST if and only if she has DMC.

3.
J Med Ethics ; 48(4): 240-243, 2022 Apr.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33637609

RESUMEN

Proponents of vaccine mandates typically claim that everyone who can be vaccinated has a moral or ethical obligation to do so for the sake of those who cannot be vaccinated, or in the interest of public health. I evaluate several previously undertheorised premises implicit to the 'obligation to vaccinate' type of arguments and show that the general conclusion is false: there is neither a moral obligation to vaccinate nor a sound ethical basis to mandate vaccination under any circumstances, even for hypothetical vaccines that are medically risk-free. Agent autonomy with respect to self-constitution has absolute normative priority over reduction or elimination of the associated risks to life. In practical terms, mandatory vaccination amounts to discrimination against healthy, innate biological characteristics, which goes against the established ethical norms and is also defeasible a priori.


Asunto(s)
Negativa a la Vacunación , Vacunas , Disentimientos y Disputas , Humanos , Obligaciones Morales , Vacunación
4.
J Med Ethics ; 48(11): 821-824, 2022 11.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34509986

RESUMEN

Taken together, Sections 145 and 63 of the Mental Health Act 1983 (MHA) provide for treatment without consent of physical illness ancillary to the mental disorder with which a patient presents. On a daily basis, clinicians make both the decision that the Act's authority can be applied to their patient's case, and that it should be applied. But in the unusual circumstances where there is uncertainty as to the applicability of the MHA to the ancillary treatment of physical illness, the assistance of a court may be sought. In so doing, the law (and thence the courts) may justify compulsion but never prescribes it; the clinician is presented with authority that he or she could use but is left to decide whether it should be employed. This paper explores how the clinical question is set before the court, and whether the distinction between symptom, manifestation and consequence is sufficiently understood. This has important consequences in the context of self-neglect and its close cousin self-harm: the question whether the relevant ailment was attributable to or exacerbated by neglect or self- inflicted harm will determine whether compulsion under the MHA is applicable; and furthermore, whether or not compulsion is clinically acceptable.


Asunto(s)
Tratamiento Involuntario , Trastornos Mentales , Femenino , Humanos , Salud Mental , Trastornos Mentales/terapia , Trastornos Mentales/psicología
5.
J Med Ethics ; 2021 May 11.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33975928

RESUMEN

Seven COVID-19 vaccines are now being distributed and administered around the world (figure correct at the time of submission), with more on the horizon. It is widely accepted that healthcare workers should have high priority. However, questions have been raised about what we ought to do if members of priority groups refuse vaccination. Using the case of influenza vaccination as a comparison, we know that coercive approaches to vaccination uptake effectively increase vaccination rates among healthcare workers and reduce patient morbidity if properly implemented. Using the principle of least restrictive alternative, we have developed an intervention ladder for COVID-19 vaccination policies among healthcare workers. We argue that healthcare workers refusing vaccination without a medical reason should be temporarily redeployed and, if their refusal persists after the redeployment period, eventually suspended, in order to reduce the risk to their colleagues and patients. This 'conditional' policy is a compromise between entirely voluntary or entirely mandatory policies for healthcare workers, and is consistent with healthcare workers' established professional, legal and ethical obligations to their patients and to society at large.

6.
J Med Ethics ; 47(10): 650-653, 2021 10.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33060185

RESUMEN

Here we present the personal perspectives of two authors on the important and unfortunately frequent scenario of ambulance clinicians facing a deceased individual and family members who do not wish them to attempt cardiopulmonary resuscitation. We examine the professional guidance and the protection provided to clinicians, which is not matched by guidance to protect family members. We look at the legal framework in which these scenarios are taking place, and the ethical issues which are presented. We consider the interaction between ethics, clinical practice and the law, and offer suggested changes to policy and guidance which we believe will protect ambulance clinicians, relatives and the patient.


Asunto(s)
Ambulancias , Reanimación Cardiopulmonar , Consenso , Familia , Humanos , Principios Morales
7.
J Med Ethics ; 46(9): 579-580, 2020 09.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32651254

RESUMEN

The COVID-19 pandemic has introduced new ethical challenges in the care of patients with serious psychiatric illness who require inpatient treatment and who may have beeen exposed to COVID-19 or have mild to moderate COVID-19 but refuse testing and adherence to infection prevention protocols. Such situations increase the risk of infection to other patients and staff on psychiatric inpatient units. We discuss medical and ethical considerations for navigating this dilemma and offer a set of policy recommendations.


Asunto(s)
Técnicas de Laboratorio Clínico , Infecciones por Coronavirus/prevención & control , Ética Médica , Hospitalización , Trastornos Mentales/complicaciones , Pandemias/prevención & control , Neumonía Viral/prevención & control , Cuarentena , Negativa a Participar , Betacoronavirus , COVID-19 , Prueba de COVID-19 , Infecciones por Coronavirus/diagnóstico , Infecciones por Coronavirus/epidemiología , Infecciones por Coronavirus/virología , Humanos , Control de Infecciones/métodos , Trastornos Mentales/terapia , Neumonía Viral/diagnóstico , Neumonía Viral/epidemiología , Neumonía Viral/virología , Políticas , Psiquiatría , SARS-CoV-2 , Aislamiento Social , Negativa del Paciente al Tratamiento
8.
J Med Ethics ; 2020 Jun 22.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32571848

RESUMEN

Whether it is morally permissible to compel women to undergo a caesarean section is a topic of longstanding debate. Despite plenty of arguments against the moral permissibility of a forced caesarean section, the question keeps cropping up. This paper seeks to scrutinise a particular moral argument in favour of compulsion: the appeal to parental obligation. We present what we take to be a distillation of the basic form of this argument. We then argue that, in the absence of an exhaustive theory of parental obligation, the question of whether a labouring woman is morally obliged to undergo emergency surgery-and especially the further question of it is morally permissible for third parties to compel this-cannot be answered via ready-made theory. We propose that the most viable option for settling both questions is by analogy. We follow earlier writers in presenting an analogous case-that of fathers being compelled to undergo non-consensual invasive surgery to save their children-but expand the analogy by considering objections that appeal to the ownership of the fetus. We offer two lines of response: (1) the parthood view of pregnancy and (2) chimaera dad. We argue that it is clear in the analogous case that compulsion cannot be justified. We also offer this analogy as a useful tool for assessing whether mothers have a moral duty to undergo caesarean sections, both in general and in particular cases, even if such a duty is insufficient to warrant compulsion.

9.
Med Health Care Philos ; 23(2): 247-252, 2020 Jun.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31960228

RESUMEN

Should we be allowed to refuse any involvement of artificial intelligence (AI) technology in diagnosis and treatment planning? This is the relevant question posed by Ploug and Holm in a recent article in Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy. In this article, I adhere to their conclusions, but not necessarily to the rationale that supports them. First, I argue that the idea that we should recognize this right on the basis of a rational interest defence is not plausible, unless we are willing to judge each patient's ideology or religion. Instead, I consider that the right must be recognized by virtue of values such as social pluralism or individual autonomy. Second, I point out that the scope of such a right should be limited at least under three circumstances: (1) if it is against a physician's obligation to not cause unnecessary harm to a patient or to not provide futile treatment, (2) in cases where the costs of implementing this right are too high, or (3) if recognizing the right would deprive other patients of their own rights to adequate health care.


Asunto(s)
Inteligencia Artificial , Técnicas y Procedimientos Diagnósticos , Planificación de Atención al Paciente/organización & administración , Negativa del Paciente al Tratamiento/psicología , Humanos , Autonomía Personal , Filosofía Médica
10.
Asian Bioeth Rev ; 12(1): 51-57, 2020 Mar.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33717330

RESUMEN

In Japan, terminating life-sustaining treatment (LST) in non-terminal patients is legally and ethically problematic given the lack of legal regulations regarding the termination of LST, including dialysis treatment. This article describes an ethically problematic case that happened at a hospital in Tokyo in March 2019, in which a patient died after a physician withdrew kidney dialysis upon the patient's request. Most national newspapers in Japan reported the case extensively and raised the question of ethical and legal permissibility of withdrawing dialysis treatment from non-terminal patients. In this article, we first examine the case within the current policy framework in Japan and then discuss how Japan can improve its end-of-life practice, focusing specifically on the patient's right to self-determination and treatment refusal. We recommend that policymakers consider legalizing the termination of LST and the patient's right to refuse treatment based on the principle of respect for autonomy.

11.
J Med Ethics ; 45(11): 742-745, 2019 11.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31413156

RESUMEN

Psychiatric inpatients with capacity may be treated paternalistically under the Mental Health Act 1983. This violates bodily autonomy and causes potentially significant harm to health and moral status, both of which may be long-lasting. I suggest that such harms may extend to killing moral persons through the impact of psychotropic drugs on psychological connectedness. Unsurprisingly, existing legislation is overwhelmingly disliked by psychiatric inpatients, the majority of whom have capacity. I present four arguments for involuntary treatment: individual safety, public safety, authentic wishes and protection of autonomy. I explore these through a case study: a patient with schizophrenia admitted to a psychiatric hospital under the Mental Health Act 1983 after an episode of self-poisoning. Through its discussion of preventative detention, the public safety argument articulates the (un)ethical underpinnings of the current position in English law. Ultimately, none of the four arguments are cogent-all fail to justify the current legal discrimination faced by psychiatric inpatients. I conclude against any use of involuntary treatment in psychiatric inpatients with capacity, endorsing the fusion approach where only psychiatric patients lacking capacity may be treated involuntarily.


Asunto(s)
Coerción , Hospitales Psiquiátricos/ética , Hospitales Psiquiátricos/organización & administración , Psiquiatría/ética , Psiquiatría/organización & administración , Internamiento Obligatorio del Enfermo Mental/ética , Internamiento Obligatorio del Enfermo Mental/legislación & jurisprudencia , Hospitales Psiquiátricos/legislación & jurisprudencia , Humanos , Pacientes Internos , Tratamiento Involuntario/ética , Competencia Mental , Autonomía Personal , Psiquiatría/legislación & jurisprudencia , Seguridad/normas
12.
J Med Ethics ; 45(12): 832-834, 2019 12.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31320406

RESUMEN

In developing their policy on paediatric medical assistance in dying (MAID), DeMichelis, Shaul and Rapoport decide to treat euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide as ethically and practically equivalent to other end-of-life interventions, particularly palliative sedation and withdrawal of care (WOC). We highlight several flaws in the authors' reasoning. Their argument depends on too cursory a dismissal of intention, which remains fundamental to medical ethics and law. Furthermore, they have not fairly presented the ethical analyses justifying other end-of-life decisions, analyses and decisions that were generally accepted long before MAID was legal or considered ethical. Forgetting or misunderstanding the analyses would naturally lead one to think MAID and other end-of-life decisions are morally equivalent. Yet as we recall these well-developed analyses, it becomes clear that approving of some forms of sedation and WOC does not commit one to MAID. Paediatric patients and their families can rationally and coherently reject MAID while choosing palliative care and WOC. Finally, the authors do not substantiate their claim that MAID is like palliative care in that it alleviates suffering. It is thus unreasonable to use this supposition as a warrant for their proposed policy.


Asunto(s)
Eutanasia , Suicidio Asistido , Niño , Ética Médica , Hospitales Pediátricos , Humanos , Cuidados Paliativos
13.
Cureus ; 10(7): e3046, 2018 Jul 25.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-30263877

RESUMEN

This case study presents a patient who has undergone right carotid endarterectomy complicated by glossopharyngeal nerve (or cranial nerve (CN) IX) injury. The patient had one transient ischaemic attack (TIA) three weeks before admission. A computed tomography (CT) scan two days after admission illustrated a right-sided parietal infarct. The patient subsequently had a CT angiogram, which showed a large, calcified plaque in the right internal carotid artery. He then underwent a right carotid endarterectomy. After the procedure, he developed dysphagia. A discussion was had with the patient about using percutaneous endoscopic gastrostomy (PEG) to provide a means of feeding. The patient subsequently refused this in favor of nasogastric tube (NGT) feeding despite the doctor's advice. This highlights an important learning point with regards to patient autonomy and their right to refuse treatment. Further research is required into the quality of life after PEG to help patients make an informed decision.

14.
J Med Ethics ; 44(1): 37-43, 2018 Jan.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-27402886

RESUMEN

This paper argues that mandatory, government-enforced vaccination can be justified even within a libertarian political framework. If so, this implies that the case for mandatory vaccination is very strong indeed as it can be justified even within a framework that, at first glance, loads the philosophical dice against that conclusion. I argue that people who refuse vaccinations violate the 'clean hands principle', a (in this case, enforceable) moral principle that prohibits people from participating in the collective imposition of unjust harm or risk of harm. In a libertarian framework, individuals may be forced to accept certain vaccines not because they have an enforceable duty to serve the common, and not because cost-benefit analysis recommends it, but because anti-vaxxers are wrongfully imposing undue harm upon others.


Asunto(s)
Disentimientos y Disputas , Libertad , Regulación Gubernamental , Programas Obligatorios/ética , Principios Morales , Vacunación , Vacunas , Humanos , Ética Basada en Principios , Negativa del Paciente al Tratamiento
15.
J Med Ethics ; 43(12): 831-840, 2017 12.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-28947505

RESUMEN

BACKGROUND: Doctors sometimes encounter parents who object to prescribed treatment for their children, and request suboptimal substitutes be administered instead (suboptimal being defined as less effective and/or more expensive). Previous studies have focused on parental refusal of treatment and when this should be permitted, but the ethics of requests for suboptimal treatment has not been explored. METHODS: The paper consists of two parts: an empirical analysis and an ethical analysis. We performed an online survey with a sample of the general public to assess respondents' thresholds for acceptable harm and expense resulting from parental choice, and the role that religion played in their judgement. We also identified and applied existing ethical frameworks to the case described in the survey to compare theoretical and empirical results. RESULTS: Two hundred and forty-two Mechanical Turk workers took our survey and there were 178 valid responses (73.6%). Respondents' agreement to provide treatment decreased as the risk or cost of the requested substitute increased (p<0.001). More than 50% of participants were prepared to provide treatment that would involve a small absolute increased risk of death for the child (<5%) and a cost increase of US$<500, respectively. Religiously motivated requests were significantly more likely to be allowed (p<0.001). Existing ethical frameworks largely yielded ambiguous results for the case. There were clear inconsistencies between the theoretical and empirical results. CONCLUSION: Drawing on both survey results and ethical analysis, we propose a potential model and thresholds for deciding about the permissibility of suboptimal treatment requests.


Asunto(s)
Actitud del Personal de Salud , Atención a la Salud/ética , Padres , Prioridad del Paciente , Relaciones Médico-Paciente/ética , Médicos , Pautas de la Práctica en Medicina/ética , Adolescente , Adulto , Anciano , Niño , Toma de Decisiones/ética , Atención a la Salud/métodos , Atención a la Salud/normas , Ética Médica , Femenino , Gastos en Salud , Humanos , Masculino , Persona de Mediana Edad , Motivación , Daño del Paciente , Religión y Medicina , Encuestas y Cuestionarios , Adulto Joven
16.
Int J Law Psychiatry ; 52: 103-110, 2017.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-28365036

RESUMEN

Severely mentally ill jail detainees require an adequate spectrum of mental health services during detainment. For some this means a limited period of treatment in a mental hospital, just as some mentally ill individuals in the community occasionally require hospital treatment. Unfortunately, this appropriate level of treatment is often denied or neglected for jail detainees with adverse consequences for them. Among the reasons for this neglect, may be standards for hospital transfer that are no longer practical and can be easily skirted by policymakers and administrators with little interest in ensuring this level of care for mentally ill jail inmates. A more realistic standard and justification would recognize the need for hospitalization for the mentally disordered detainee who because of psychotic anosognosia refuses appropriate treatment including medications and/or whose severely decompensated condition is worsening or failing to improve despite attempts at treatment in the jail.


Asunto(s)
Internamiento Obligatorio del Enfermo Mental/normas , Prisioneros , Criminales/legislación & jurisprudencia , Criminales/psicología , Psiquiatría Forense/normas , Humanos , Trastornos Mentales/diagnóstico , Trastornos Mentales/terapia , Derechos del Paciente/legislación & jurisprudencia , Derechos del Paciente/normas , Estados Unidos
17.
J Med Ethics ; 43(8): 489-494, 2017 08.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-28062650

RESUMEN

The Belgian model of 'integral' end-of-life care consists of universal access to palliative care (PC) and legally regulated euthanasia. As a first worldwide, the Flemish PC organisation has embedded euthanasia in its practice. However, some critics have declared the Belgian-model concepts of 'integral PC' and 'palliative futility' to fundamentally contradict the essence of PC. This article analyses the various essentialistic arguments for the incompatibility of euthanasia and PC. The empirical evidence from the euthanasia-permissive Benelux countries shows that since legalisation, carefulness (of decision making) at the end of life has improved and there have been no significant adverse 'slippery slope' effects. It is problematic that some critics disregard the empirical evidence as epistemologically irrelevant in a normative ethical debate. Next, rejecting euthanasia because its prevention was a founding principle of PC ignores historical developments. Further, critics' ethical positions depart from the PC tenet of patient centeredness by prioritising caregivers' values over patients' values. Also, many critics' canonical adherence to the WHO definition of PC, which has intention as the ethical criterion is objectionable. A rejection of the Belgian model on doctrinal grounds also has nefarious practical consequences such as the marginalisation of PC in euthanasia-permissive countries, the continuation of clandestine practices and problematic palliative sedation until death. In conclusion, major flaws of essentialistic arguments against the Belgian model include the disregard of empirical evidence, appeals to canonical and questionable definitions, prioritisation of caregiver perspectives over those of patients and rejection of a plurality of respectable views on decision making at the end of life.


Asunto(s)
Actitud , Toma de Decisiones/ética , Disentimientos y Disputas , Principios Morales , Cuidados Paliativos/ética , Suicidio Asistido/ética , Cuidado Terminal/ética , Actitud del Personal de Salud , Actitud Frente a la Muerte , Actitud Frente a la Salud , Bélgica , Cuidadores , Teoría Ética , Eutanasia , Humanos , Suicidio Asistido/legislación & jurisprudencia , Cuidado Terminal/legislación & jurisprudencia
18.
J Med Ethics ; 43(7): 450-454, 2017 07.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-27582080

RESUMEN

In this paper, I explore under what circumstances it might be morally acceptable to transplant organs from a patient lacking capacity. I argue, with a developed hypothetical based around a mother and son, that (1) 'Best interests' should be interpreted broadly to include the interests that people have previously expressed in the well-being of others. It could, therefore, be in the 'best interests' of an unconscious patient to donate a non-vital organ to a family member. (2) Further expanding upon this case, and developing a variation on the 'trolley problems' I argue that where it is inevitable that an incapacitous patient is going to die-and specifically when it has been agreed through the courts that a patient in a permanent vegetative state is going to have clinically assisted nutrition and hydration withdrawn (with the inevitable consequence of death, and causing desiccation of the organs such that they are no longer able to be donated)-it could be in a patient's best interests to actively end their life with a drug that would stop the heart both to minimise potential suffering and in order to be able to have vital organs donated. I argue that in this case the strict adherence to the distinction between acts and omissions is not in the patient's best interests and should be reconsidered.


Asunto(s)
Estado de Conciencia , Toma de Decisiones/ética , Cuidados para Prolongación de la Vida/ética , Trasplante de Órganos/ética , Estado Vegetativo Persistente , Donantes de Tejidos , Privación de Tratamiento/ética , Disentimientos y Disputas , Familia , Humanos , Cuidados para Prolongación de la Vida/legislación & jurisprudencia , Principios Morales , Trasplante de Órganos/legislación & jurisprudencia , Privación de Tratamiento/legislación & jurisprudencia
19.
J Med Ethics ; 43(4): 264-265, 2017 04.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-26934911

RESUMEN

One of the great merits of On Complicity and Compromise is that it wades into specific swamps where ordinary theorists fear to slog. It is persuasive that in general it can be right sometimes to be complicit in wrongdoing by others through causally contributing to the wrongdoing, but not sharing its purpose, if by being involved one can reasonably expect to lessen the extent of the wrong that would otherwise be suffered by the victims. I focus on whether the book's general thesis is applicable to torture, which depends on what torture and the torture situation are in fact like. I focus on the case to which the chapter several times refers: the innovative CIA paradigm of torture. First, to the extent that the paradigm, which is predominantly mental, or psychological, torture succeeds in its goal of producing regression to a compliant state, the physician would be unable to rely on the torture victim's expressions of preferences or interests as authentically his own. Second, since disorientation plays such a large role in the CIA's style of torture (adopted at Guantanamo by the military), the authorities would refuse to allow a stable relationship to be built up with any one doctor by any victim, making comprehension of the victim's preferences difficult. Third, even if the doctor could somehow judge what the victim's genuine interests were, the control of the situation is much too totalistic to allow the physician any action independent of what the torture regime requires.


Asunto(s)
Relativismo Ético , Violaciones de los Derechos Humanos , Medicina Militar/ética , Médicos , Mala Conducta Profesional/ética , Tortura/ética , Complicidad , Ética Médica , Violaciones de los Derechos Humanos/ética , Violaciones de los Derechos Humanos/legislación & jurisprudencia , Humanos , Rol del Médico , Médicos/ética , Médicos/legislación & jurisprudencia , Prisioneros , Estrés Psicológico
20.
J Med Ethics ; 43(7): 459-468, 2017 07.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-27663784

RESUMEN

Life-extending treatment, in the form of artificial nutrition and hydration, is often provided to people in permanent vegetative states (PVS) in England and Wales for many years, even when their family believes the patient would not want it and despite the fact that no court in the UK has ever found in favour of continuing such treatment for a patient with a confirmed PVS diagnosis. The first half of this article presents a close analysis of the recent case of Cumbria NHS Clinical Commissioning Group v Miss S and Ors [2016] EWCOP 32. It examines the causes of delay in bringing this case to court and reaching a final judgment. It draws not only on the published judgment, but also on the two authors' involvement in supporting the family (before, during and subsequent to the court hearings) as a result of their academic and policy-related work in this area. This includes conversations with the family and with members of the clinical and legal teams, and observations in court. The second part of the article draws out the ethical and practical implications of the findings for theory and policy and suggests ways forward in relation to (a) the provision and inspection of care for these patients; (b) legal practice in relation to 'best interests' and (c) the perceived requirement under English law for a court application before life-prolonging treatment can be withdrawn from PVS patients-even in the absence of any 'in principle' opposition.


Asunto(s)
Estado de Conciencia , Toma de Decisiones/ética , Cuidados para Prolongación de la Vida/ética , Estado Vegetativo Persistente , Privación de Tratamiento/ética , Disentimientos y Disputas , Inglaterra , Humanos , Jurisprudencia , Cuidados para Prolongación de la Vida/legislación & jurisprudencia , Principios Morales , Políticas , Medicina Estatal , Gales , Privación de Tratamiento/legislación & jurisprudencia
SELECCIÓN DE REFERENCIAS
DETALLE DE LA BÚSQUEDA